the law of his or her jurisdiction. Appellate court decisions ofthis nature, capable
of restraining the judges fact-finding freedom, are legion in most jurisdictions.
But this is only part of the story. Restrictions of the judicial fact-finding freedom
can also emanate from rules barring the use of evidence obtained in violation of
basic human rights. As is well known, rules of this genre have mushroomed in the
aftermath of the traumatic experience with totalitarian and autocratic regimes of the
past century. On first inspection it seems that rules prohibiting the use of illegally
obtained evidence are unrelated to the judges’ freedom in processing evidence:
they only narrow the pool of information available to them, and have nothing to
do with the evaluation of evidence remaining in the pool. But this analytically
correct observation misses the mark in situations in which judges become exposed
to reliable but illegally obtained information that cannot fail but produce an impact
on their mind. In this situation rules devoted to the admissibility of evidence mutate
sub silentio into rules dealing with the evaluation of evidence, requiring judges to
attribute no probative value to evidence that has affected their thinking. But can
judges disregard knowledge that has been lodged in their mind? The answer depends
on the character of psychological operations involved in evidence processing. If
judges are capable of reasoning by attaching separate value to items of information,
and then coming to a conclusion by aggregating or disaggregating these values,
they can follow the law’s mandate and attribute no probative value to prohibited
evidence. Empirical evidence suggests, however, that it is difficult for humans to
disentangle the value of discrete information from global judgments, and to process
received information in monadic fashion. It is true that when properly obtained
evidence is clearly insufficient for conviction, the law’s mandate to exclude illegal
but reliable evidence can be effective: judges must acquit the defendant. But when
properly obtained evidence is compelling, they face a predicament: unless they
recuse themselves, they must imagine what a judge uncontaminated by illegal
information would decide. Would this hypothetical judge, they must ask themselves,
find untainted evidence sufficient for conviction? Observe, however, that even if
they successfully switch to this third person’s viewpoint, their decision no longer
rests on their personal conviction which is in many jurisdictions a sine qua non.
The third person perspective may even call for a factual finding contrary to what
judges actually believe on the basis of illegal but credible information. It would thus
not be surprising if empirical research revealed that in advancing reasons for their
factual findings many judges simply omit any reference to illegal evidence even if it
has actually influenced their verdict.’ Briefly, then, the exclusion of illegally obtained